Saturday, February 13, 2016

The Demeaning of Life...Part III

The fourth installment of what started out in the spring of 2012 as a hand-written essay about a number of controversial issues that I’d been stewing over for years—in particular, “problems” with current speculations regarding the origin of life, quandaries raised by the very nature of biological complexity, and what I saw as the shortcomings of a neo-Darwinian insistence on natural selection being almost solely the cause of all evolutionary change. Four years of subsequent evolutionary research have confirmed my suspicions that neo-Darwinism has presented an oversimplified picture of what is actually a very complex subject—one not so simple and clear-cut as authors like Richard Dawkins would have us believe. This short section is the first of several historical overviews that reveal how various biological fields have been strongly affected by the prevailing attitudes of earlier, formative times. Throughout this work I’ll be attempting to show how the slew of amazing advances in recent decades point to an entirely new way of viewing life…and how the strictly materialistic stance taken by almost all contemporary biologists doesn’t square with a bigger picture gradually being revealed by all their new findings. (The next section will look into the failings of scientific materialism, with its over-reliance on purely reductive thinking.)


III.  The Modern Synthesis


The most developed science remains a continual becoming, and in every field nonbalance plays a functional role of prime importance since it necessitates re-equilibrium.
          
                                         Jean Piaget, The Development of Thought

The bedrock assumptions upon which Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection rests are that there can be random variations in genetic material and that these can lead to improved chances for survival. The late paleontologist and evolutionary biologist Stephen Jay Gould, summarizing its main tenets:

First, that all organisms produce more offspring than can possibly survive; second, that all organisms within a species vary, one from the other; third, that at least some of this variation is inherited by offspring. From these three facts, we infer the principal of natural selection: since only some of the offspring can survive, on average the survivors will be those variants that, by good fortune, are better adapted to changing local environments. Since these offspring will inherit the favorable variations of their parents, organisms of the next generation will, on average, become better adapted to local conditions.


During the period Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace were shoring up their ground-breaking theories, neither they nor anyone else had any idea how inconceivably complex the manifold workings of life actually were. As an illustration of how little was understood it that era: German biologist Ernst Haeckel, a contemporary and great admirer of Darwin’s, believed that the cell (still a little-known entity) was “not composed of any organs at all, but consist[ed] entirely of shapeless, simple, homogeneous matter…nothing more than a shapeless, mobile, little lump of mucus or slime….”

While Darwin and Wallace were occupied with refining their ideas, a congenial and self-effacing Austrian friar was growing pea plants in his abbey’s garden.[1] Over the course of eight years, Gregor Mendel patiently reared almost 30,000 plants while piecing together the foundation of modern genetics.[2]

Due to a number of adverse historical circumstances, Mendel’s far-reaching insights went unrecognized for nearly half a century. Significantly, after all his painstaking labor and meticulous recording of data, the priest’s findings were made known solely through two public lectures followed by a paper submitted to the Proceedings of the  Natural Science Society of Brünn. Aside from that one obscure 1866 publication, Mendel personally distributed 40 reprints of the treatise to suitable people and…his seminal  research quickly all but disappeared. It was ignored by fellow botanists; they were confused about the object of it all… perceived the work as being merely about hybridization (the controlled breeding of animals being an important feature of their day-to-day lives), and were put off by Mendel’s perplexing reliance on numbers. It seems odd today, but scientifically rigorous experimentation involving statistics was a foreign concept to biologists of that era.

His efforts were largely forgotten until 1900, when three European plant physiologists, independently performing similar experiments, simultaneously brought to light the friar’s enormous contribution to science. Mendel’s treatise, Experiments with Plant Hybrids, had been published seven years after the first edition of On the Origin of Species came out but, despite an apocryphal story that Darwin owned a copy but never read it, there is no evidence he was aware of the work.[3] (Some scholars believe that Darwin, whose mathematical skills were poor, would likely not have recognized its implications.) Mendel, long in poor health, died at only sixty-one. All his papers, all his scrupulous documentation, were carted out to a hill behind the abbey shortly after his death…and summarily burned.[4] 

The discovery of genes as discrete units of inheritance had a huge effect on accelerating evolutionary research. In the 1920s and 30s, following the acceptance of chromosome theory, a new discipline emerged: population genetics (the study, heavy on statistical analysis, of how traits arise and move through populations). Thanks largely to work by two Britons—statistician Ronald Fischer and biologist J.B.S. Haldane—and American geneticist Sewall Wright, Mendelian genetics and the concept of evolution by natural selection were finally integrated: a unification that became feasible only after it was finally recognized that the gradual, steady modification called for by Darwin’s theory was entirely compatible with Mendel’s axioms. This paved the way for an end to various disagreements that had been building for some time. These conflicts were for the most part put to rest during the course of an international symposium held at Princeton in 1947, shortly after WW II’s travel restrictions had lifted. It became known as the modern Darwinian synthesis.

The modern synthesis is basically a set of ideas that was assertively championed by bird taxonomist-cum-evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr and several of his chief collaborators in America, notably paleontologist George Gaylord Simpson, expatriate Soviet geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky, and botanist G. Ledyard Stebbins—all prominent experts in their fields. Up until that time, researchers working in disciplines such as paleontology, systematics, and ecology were neither in close communication nor sharing their findings. To some extent, these fields were all influenced by Darwinian theory even though many of his ideas had long since fallen out of favor. The specific disciplines’ views on evolutionary agencies and their relative importance had diverged; each was starting to attribute different meanings to established concepts and use different terminology to describe them. Of even greater concern, paleontologists were actually at odds with the concept of natural selection as a consequence of not seeing the gradual changes required by its precepts reflected in fossil records. Those working with population genetics were convinced they had finally found a way to connect the different disciplines.

The symposium, considered a great success, united many branches of biology under one common evolutionary umbrella that (according to Gould) “validated natural selection as a powerful causative agent and raised it from a former status as one of a contender among many to a central position among mechanisms of change.” (This was the gathering’s intended goal.) Mayr made clear that the intention of the synthesis was simply a means to
                                     
designate the general acceptance of two conclusions: gradual evolution can be explained in terms of small genetic changes (“mutations”) and recombination, and the ordering of this genetic variation by natural selection; and the observed evolutionary phenomena, particularly macroevolutionary processes and speciation, can be explained in a manner that is consistent with known genetic mechanisms.


The true significance and influence of natural selection was still being debated until findings by Dobzhansky reaffirmed its primacy—a critical, solidifying event in the movement’s early development. The alliance thereafter commonly became known as neo-Darwinism.[5] But, like Darwin and his contemporaries, Mayr and his esteemed colleagues had little notion of the real complexities lying beneath the surface of their subject matter. The entire  field of microbiology was in its infancy…the helical structure of DNA still unknown. No embryologists had attended the symposium and their findings would muddy the water for some time yet. Perhaps due to the strong personalities and fervor of neo-Darwinism’s promoters, from its outset the movement was infused with a zealousness that made it notably resistant to change—an ironic misfortune, since all the scientific branches concerned were in flux.

Only fifty years later, the modern synthesis was in need of modernization.             


©2016 by Tim Forsell           draft                                                                                                                  
        18 Jan 2016                                                     





[1] Properly speaking, he was from Moravia (a historic region in what is now the Czech Republic). Many misconceptions surround Mendel and his work: for one, he was a friar—not a monk—and  lived not at a monastery but at an abbey, among a community of very talented and learned men.
[2] It was fortuitous that Mendel chose to work with pea plants. By sheer good fortune, the traits he chose to follow were controlled by genes found on different chromosomes and those traits also happened to denote distinct, unambiguous features not typically displayed in such regular fashion. Botanist Carl Nägeli (1817–91) was the only biologist to attempt repeating Mendel’s experiments. Unfortunately, he chose to work with a plant in the Sunflower family that reproduces asexually and thus did not demonstrate Mendel’s results.
[3] Mendel and his peers were all well-acquainted with Darwin’s work. (Mendel owned a copy of Origin.)
[4] The complicated story of the “rediscovery” of Mendel’s research is somewhat out of the scope of this work but historically fascinating: Mendel’s obscure publication had been passed around by a few plant breeders. Among those who had read the paper were Dutchman Hugo de Vries, German Carl Correns, and Austrian Erich von Tschermak. Working independently, each achieved in their own experiments results similar to Mendel’s. Correns barely missed out on beating de Vries to publication and there is evidence that both intended to claim discovery of what became  known as Mendel’s Law (the 3:1 ratio of dominant versus recessive characteristics generated by the hybridization of two purebred strains). Coincidently, de Vries sent Correns a copy of his newly-published article, written for a French journal, that made no mention of Mendel. Correns was just then putting the last touches on his own manuscript and, bitter at having been upstaged, hurriedly finished his own paper and sent it to the German Botanical Society for publication. Correns made a point of crediting Mendel with the 3:1 law’s discovery to undercut de Vries’ claim to priority; whether or not he intended to do the same is still debated. But, unbeknownst to Correns, de Vries had already sent his paper to the German Botanical Society and, in this version, had credited Mendel. Thus was Mendel’s work “rediscovered” and handed over to science. 
[5] George Romanes, a protégé of Darwin’s, “coined the term neo-Darwinism to refer to the version of evolution advocated by Alfred Russell Wallace and August Weismann with its heavy dependence on natural selection…[rejecting] the Lamarckian idea of inheritance of acquired characteristics” (a commonly held notion of the era that Darwin himself had embraced).